Michael Travis BA/LLB (Hons) June 2001, University of Auckland Law School Please notify the author if you wish to cite this paper, or use extracts in your work. A PDF is also available via Google Drive. Biological positivism suffers from the same problems inherent in positivist criminology at large. As described in the quote from Gottfredson and Hirschi, the ultimate contribution of biological positivism so far has been to illustrate some mere correlation between biological variables and crime rates. In terms of the objectives set by these theorists, this must be considered a failure of the ‘empirical determinism’ concept to fit criminal offending overall. However, does this necessarily deprive biological positivism of any utility?
The
fact that the theories have not proven to be the perfect solution to
criminology does not mean that they are without value. Afterall, "[t]he
suggestion that there is any possibility of one single explanation of criminal
behaviour has to be totally rejected because not only is behaviour complex,
crime is a social construct which changes over time and across cultures." [1]
A holistic
look at the various social sciences that comprise criminology shows that each
area of discipline has its flaws – but that each contributes in a valuable way
to the overall discourse. Biological positivism is no exception, and in fact
may be limited only by our present scientific knowledge.
To
illustrate this point I shall:
i)
criticise
the general flaws of the positivist method,
ii)
provide
a history of biological positivism,
iii)
illustrate
the errors within each theory, and
iv)
describe
the leftover value of the theory.
The Positivist
Revolution, and the flaws of the positivist method.
Enrico
Ferri envisaged a systematic removal of the free will metaphysics of classical
criminology, which he intended to replace with a “science of society” aimed at
the elimination of crime. This would be “an approach geared only to practical ends
… and not cluttered with irrelevant, philosophical, retributory and
ethicoreligious beliefs.” [2]
Guerry
provided this similar mission statement:
“The time has gone when we could claim to regulate
society by laws established solely on metaphysical theories and [an] ideal type
... [of] absolute justice. Laws are not made for men in the abstract ... but
for real men, placed in precisely determined circumstances.”
The
new approach was thus intended to discover “the determined, law-governed nature
of human action” [3]
via the scientific method (be it biological, social or statistical).
Consequently it would suffer from the assumptions imbedded in the scientific
method itself, namely belief in:
i)
the
quantification of behaviour,
ii)
scientific
neutrality, and
iii)
the
determinism of behaviour.
The quantification of behaviour.
This
was a faith in the scientific measurement of phenomena – but it became rapidly
difficult for positivists to quantify ‘criminal behaviour’, especially as a
contrast to ‘normal’ behaviour. Positivists turned to criminal statistics, and
a search for the ‘moral yardstick’.
Both
sought to illustrate some community consensus by which ‘normal’ and ‘criminal’
behaviour could be defined. Liberal positivists believed that “[i]n democratic
countries there [would be] little scope for large differences between the
definitions of the majority of the people and the encoded definitions.” [4] In other
words, positivists needed only to look at the law for a realistic codification
of criminality. This, of course, is an error that positivists had already
condemned in the classicists…
Meanwhile,
radical positivists such as Raffaele Garofalo believed that a community
consensus would exist regardless of codification. However this appeal to the
“injury to so much of the moral sense” was no more than an invocation of moral
sensibilities. Garofalo, condemns Gabriel Tarde, attempted to “cast [his]
anchor in what is the most fluid and evasive thing in the world … feeling.”
Scientific
neutrality.
This
was the assumption that science would provide an objective, non-biased vantage
point from which to assess society. However, it appears to be no more than
an assumption. It should be obvious that even professed ‘objectivists’ are
capable of rendering value judgments; and moreover, it a well-known modern
principle of science that there is no longer such thing as the purely objective
‘observer’ because:
i)
every
observation is tainted by the observer itself, and
ii)
the
language used to express it taints the expression of an observation.
As
described by Young:
“The [experts] must explain what
is perceived as unusual in terms of the values associated by their audience as
usual ... they circumscribe and negate the reality of values different from
their own. They do not explain, but merely explain away.”
Determinism
of behaviour.
This
was the belief that deviancy must be subject to discoverable causal laws. It
has been criticised for defusing deviancy as a lack of choice, and of reifying
human endeavour, with no recognition of moral choice or creativity.
Conclusion
In
general terms there are problems with the postulates of positivism. For
example, the idea of the consensus worldview denies the role of ethics, and the
‘neutral’ language of science allows political and commercial exploiters to
“use the social sciences as a front which helps them control public opinions
and … responses.” [5]
This
misguided belief in the perceived ‘purity’ of empirical research must be
considered in any look at the work of biological positivists.
Biological
Positivism, and theories.
Cesare
Lombroso and Atavism.
Cesare
Lombroso’s groundbreaking work was a direct reversal of the statistical method
employed by Quetelet and Guerry. His atavistic theory effectively argued that
the nature of the criminal determines the character of the institution, and not
vice-versa.
His
theory of criminal anthropology was also very popular during its inception,
since “L’Uomo Delinquente (Criminal Man)” (1876) was published short
after Darwin’s “Origin of the Species” (1859). Lindesmith explains:
“It may be that the theory of
the born criminal offered a convenient
rationalisation of the failure of preventive effort
and an escape from the implications of the dangerous doctrine that crime is an
essential product of our social organisation.”
Darwin,
then, first suggested atavism, when he wrote:
“With mankind some of the worst
dispositions which occasionally without any assignable cause make their
appearance in families, may perhaps be reversions to a savage state, from which
we are not removed by many generations.”
Lombroso,
who was busy studying the physical characteristics of criminals and soldiers,
claimed to have discovered proof of this supposition in a “flash of
inspiration” while studying the skull of famous brigand, Vihella:
“[T]he problem of the nature of the
criminal – an atavistic being who reproduces in his person the ferocious
instincts of primitive humanity and the inferior animals.”
One
could further determine the people in this category of evolutionary ‘throwbacks’
by their “enormous jaws, high cheek bones … insensibility to pain” and even
behavioural traits, such as “tattooing, excessive idleness [and] love of
orgies”, all of which led to “the irresistible craving for evil for its own
sake.”
Lombroso
was faced with some criticism of this blanket description, and later developed
other types of criminal. Alongside the minority born killer / atavist, he
added:
i)
the
epileptic criminal,
ii)
the
insane criminal, and
iii)
the
occasional criminal – called ‘criminaloids’ (those with trace elements of
atavism, who could be drawn into crime through criminal association, or poor
education etc), and
iv)
criminals
of passion (compelled to crime by temporarily irresistible urges, eg love,
honour, rage).
To
the modern eye, however, several flaws present themselves. Lombroso’s theories
were found to be statistically unsound, with no recognition of environmental
factors on the individual’s physical development. Charles Gorring wrote
criticisms of the lack of an absolute distinction between criminals, and
non-criminals. Meanwhile, the
evolutionary ‘throwback’ concept has since proved to be actually
impossible; and Lombroso also ignored the stigmatising effect of physical
differences, whereby criminal offending is encouraged through exposure to
negative social interaction:
“It seems likely that the attitudes
offenders hold about themselves, their peers and crime itself will play a large
part in the decision-making process before offending behaviour occurs.” [6]
Or,
from literature:
“I,
that am rudely stamp'd, and want love's majesty … Cheated of feature by
dissembling nature, Deformed, unfinish'd, sent before my time … And therefore
since I cannot prove a lover … I am determined to prove a villain.” [7]
Most
dangerously though, this type of theory has been used to support arguments
favouring eugenics – for example, the Nazi Party used to demonstrate that
biological devolution was present in the skulls of Jewish people. This of
course justified their execution. (One mustn’t forget that this was also the
ultimate conclusion of Garofalo’s work – that criminal eugenics should be
employed in the artificial removal of offenders.)
Simply
put, and this is a recurring flaw amongst biological positivists, biology alone
cannot explain crime rates. Nonetheless, Lombroso’s work was subsequently
followed by other similar studies, such as those by John Casper Lavater (facial
features) and Franz Joseph Gall (head-shapes, or phrenology).
Kretschmer
/ Sheldon, and Body Typing.
This
theory proposes that disposition (including criminality) is relative to body
types, of which there are three:
i)
endomorphic:
a soft and round body type, typified as slow, comfort-loving, and extroverted,
ii)
mesomorphic:
a hard and round body type, typified as aggressive and active, and
iii)
ectomorphic:
the fragile and thin body type, typified as self-restrained and introverted.
Consequently,
people with mesomorphic body types make up the highest percentage of our prison
populations.
Conrad’s
contribution to this theory was to point out that mesomorphs are on a lower
level of “ontogenetic development” than the others. In other words, their
makeup is similar to that of children, therefore they must suffer from
psychological immaturity.
This
theory fails to recognise a couple of major factors. It doesn’t discuss the
environmental effect on physical development (such as the effect of a
lower-class diet), and ignores the fact that delinquent subcultures recruit new
members selectively (gangs prefer to recruit physically fit members, thus
mesomorphs). Like Lombroso’s theory it also ignores the stigmatic effect of
body type on social interaction.
XXY
Chromosome theory.
The
chromosome pairing of an ordinary female is XX, and for a male, XY. However,
there are naturally occurring variations on the standard, for example the
‘pairing’ XXY, known as Klinefelter’s
Syndrome. There seem to be certain physical characteristics that flow from an
unusual chromosome ‘pairing’; people with Klinefelter’s Syndrome, for example,
often display lower intelligence. Inevitably, biological theorists began to
look for a chromosome arrangement to explain criminal behaviour – they came up
with the XXY arrangement (though some disagreed; most notably Price, who
believed an extra Y to be more relevant).
Following
surveys of convicted offenders it was decided that criminals with an XXY pair
were:
i)
severe
psychopaths,
ii)
convicted
at a younger age than other offenders, and
iii)
tended
to commit property (not personal) crimes, and
iv)
came
from non-criminal backgrounds and upbringings.
However,
the usual criticisms can be made with regard to these findings. For example, an
XXY pair also leads to pronounced physical development, and the same
stigmatising effects discussed previously. The research also only accounts for
a small portion of overall offenders; and is, at any rate, “manifestly a very
crude theory.” [8]
Conclusion
The
dilemma faced by biological positivists is this: no single biological theory
seems sufficient to explain all criminal offending. Furthermore, the
instruments of science are not always precise – historically, science often
corrects itself (for example, the subsequent disproving of the ‘throwback’
theory as an impossibility). As a consequence, even those who recognise the
potential value of this discipline (or are “scholars friendly to the idea of
biological causation”) must tread carefully, lest they embrace a theory that is
incomplete or scientifically inaccurate.
There
are also more general aversions to theories of determinism – Taylor claims that
“total determinism palpably contradicts the ‘feel’ of human existence,” and
that it is inconsistent with our democratic ideology. While there may be
substance in determinist theory, it is perhaps dangerous from the social
control point of view – in that it removes moral choice, and discourages
individuals from striving for ‘good’. In other words, it can arm people with an
excuse for their actions, just as it arms the policy makers:
“[I]t is used to back up arguments
and proposals, it is selected for quotation at the appropriate, strategic time
and place.” [9]
It
seems to me, and this is a point I strived to emphasise in my introduction,
that there is indeed value in a “practical inquiry into the criminal
manifestations of individual and social life” [10]. It
must, however, strive to be more than absurd reduction of the whole question of
criminal offending into descriptions of brain activity, or genetic
predisposition. Biological positivism must stand alongside psychological,
social, and structural theories of crime if it is to be of any realistic use.
|
Saturday, 16 June 2001
A Critique of Biological Positivism
Labels:
Michael Travis,
writing
Location:
Auckland, New Zealand
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
i just asking if it ok to use this to discuss biological positivism for my university class
ReplyDelete