Michael Travis BA/LLB (Hons)
June 2001, University of Auckland Law School
Please notify the author if you wish to cite this paper, or use extracts in your work. A PDF is also available via Google Drive.
June 2001, University of Auckland Law School
Please notify the author if you wish to cite this paper, or use extracts in your work. A PDF is also available via Google Drive.
Torstein Eckhoff’s essay “Justifications of Punishment” [1] makes it clear that he believes punishment (for criminal offending) should only be employed where the results are both just, and useful. Therefore, by contrast, he asserts that there should be no punishment if the results are lacking in any way – for example, where the use of punishment is:
i)
neither just
or useful,
ii)
just, but
without use, or
iii)
useful, but
unjust.
There are of
course various proponents of conflicting theories on this matter. Kant, for
example, asserts justice as the only relevant factor when deciding whether or
not to inflict punishment, while the utilitarians (obviously) assert utility as
being the major relevant factor.
To more
clearly understand the scope of this argument, and to help define my own
opinion on the matter, I will attempt to give an account of the origins and
purposes of punishment, and then weigh up the balance between justice and
utility.
Origins of
law and punishment.
Historically,
punishment was meted out as a ‘self-help’ remedy to a criminal offence. In
classical Rome this was called lex talionis (retributive justice). Many
offences such as assault or theft were delicta privatis (private
offences), and only treason, murder, and destruction of public property were crimina
publica (state offences).
Similarly,
early Anglo Saxons enforced the criminal law through private blood feuds (which
could spark an endless chain of feuding), banishments, tariffs and so on. This
feudal system evolved into a scheme whereby victims would be monetarily
compensated by the offender in the case of murder, assault, and so on.
Eventually,
as in Ancient Rome, the criminal law was secularised, and in the 12th
Century a common law emerged. Under the common law, punishment moved again from
the financial to the physical as the state assumed the role of punisher.
Convicted offenders could now be executed, imprisoned or branded. Consequently,
a wrongdoer could no longer be ‘saved’ by private settlement.
The purpose
of the criminal law (a modern analysis).
Law operates
as a mechanism for social control and the regulation of conduct, and should
attempt to reflect “the fundamental social values” of society (realistically,
these are determined by the majority). [2]
Consequently, punishment is often thought to be the method by which these
values should be reinforced, and by which we can secure compliance with the
law.
This
requires the identification of ‘criminalised’ conduct,
as well as an evaluation of who should be punished, and to what extent. This is
the area in which opinions seem to differ. Clarkson gives the example of
penalising traffic offences with life imprisonment - if prevention is the sole
aim of a legal system, then this punishment will probably secure total compliance
with the law, because it is so excessive.
However, if
justice (or just deserts, as defined by proportionality) is also an aim, this
penalty should be considered too severe for the crime. Punishing illegal
parking with life imprisonment would therefore be unjust. As classical theory
describes it, “punishments must be proportional to the interests violated by
the crime.” [3]
So what are
the reasons behind punishment? A penal system may try to incorporate any number
of the following goals:
i)
denunciation:
a ‘marking’ of the fact that a law has been transgressed as a way of showing
disapproval,
ii)
education:
to teach an offender that they have transgressed, and how to prevent future
offending,
iii)
retribution:
punishment as a reciprocal action, i.e. just deserts,
iv)
reform: to
rehabilitate an offender so that they will not re-offend (similar to
education),
v)
incapacitation:
to prevent recidivism by killing, or physically and spatially restraining the
offender,
vi)
deterrence:
by preventing crime through the fear of its penalties (supposedly more
effective when would-be criminals can see others being punished),
vii)
prevention:
a combination of previous factors in the hope of preventing new or
re-offending, and
viii)
justice?
Justice
and/or Utility.
Eckhoff:
“The justification of punishment has usually
been based either on utilitarian considerations or on principles of retributive
justice. Through history, the pendulum has moved back and forth between these
two approaches.”
Both useful
and just.
If
punishment is both useful, and just, what could possibly be presented as an
objection? First we must determine what we mean by ‘useful’. Obviously
punishment is ‘useful’ if it meets any of the goals delineated above. But the
influences of these goals differ from society to society – so which goals must
be satisfied before we can justify using punishment? Ultimately they all point
towards prevention – either by would-be offenders, or by previously convicted
offenders. This implies that any degree of prevention is enough to meet the
definition of ‘useful’. This, in fact, is the hurdle that liberalists ask us to
account for – as per John Stuart Mill (1859):
“The only purpose for which power can be
rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his
will, is to prevent harm to others.”
This,
though, requires us to now ask what defines ‘harm’. Is it ‘the violation of the
interests of others’ [4],
or is harm against the common morality too broad a definition? Feinberg (1984) offers the ‘thwarting,
setting back, or defeating of an interest’ as a consequence of a wrongful
action. But what is ‘wrongful’? This discussion can quickly become
tautological.
When we look
closer at this discussion of ‘harm’, we can begin to see a connection with
Eckhoff’s method of authorising punishment. Clarkson describes ‘harm’ (or deep
offence) as a minimal condition - one must also “establish that use of the
criminal law is necessary and profitable.” Necessity thus requires an
exhaustion of other solutions – where harms might be prevented without
requiring recourse to punishment. For example, combating the smoking of
cigarettes with education and advertisement, rather than prohibition. [5]
What should
be considered is that, where punishment may well be just and useful, there is
the possibility of other avenues of response. As per Clarkson:
“The criminal law should never be invoked
unless there is no other way of dealing with the problem.”
This merits
a strong case for the concept of restorative justice, which sacrifices the
state monopoly on retribution, and allows the parties to determine their own
‘justice’ (as was historically possible). This also allows for a form of
rehabilitative justice, as both facing up to a victim, and avoiding
incarceration (and criminal association) may ‘restore’ the offender as well as
the victim. Eckhoff, unfortunately, categorically denies the possible
effectiveness of this scheme:
“[I]t is not reasonable to expect anything
different and better given the extended trial that rehabilitation has had …
Rehabilitative theories have lost their credibility.”
This strikes
me as being a very blasé statement. Eckhoff doesn’t really wish to deal with
rehabilitative justice so dismisses it out of hand, despite his own recognition
that “supporters of rehabilitation will perhaps say that it has never been
given a proper chance.” This is exactly the argument advanced by proponents of
rehabilitative justice. Subsequently, the idea has been gathering support in
many Western countries, and New Zealand has recently adopted a pilot scheme
(which, by all accounts is proving both popular and successful). [6]
Just, but
without use.
Where there
appear to be no practical or physical benefits to be derived from punishment,
it has been argued that justice alone provides reason enough. This argument
places its emphasis on retribution. Eckhoff believes there to be two
approaches, that of:
i)
strong
retribution: evil must be repaid by evil (a restoration of moral balance), or
ii)
weak
retribution: evil may be repaid by evil (includes a consideration of utility).
Immanuel
Kant was a strong proponent of the former:
“[W]hoever has committed murder, must die.
There is … no juridical substitute or surrogate, that can be given or taken for
the satisfaction of justice.” [7]
Kant is also
quite willing to punish in the absence of any practical utility, as evidenced
by this example:
“Even if a civil society resolved to dissolve
itself … the last murderer lying in the prison ought to be executed before the
resolution was carried out ... in order that every one may realize the desert
of his deeds, and that blood-guiltiness may not remain upon the people; for
otherwise they might all be regarded as participators in the murder as a public
violation of justice.”
Eckhoff
simply denounces this idea as “one-sided and brutal”, and notes that it “does
not appeal to [his] sense of justice.” Nicola Lacey provides a more
independent, and thus relevant, criticism in her response paper [8].
Kant, she says, is “mystifyingly metaphorical”, but that theories of
retribution are strengthened by being placed in “the context of a broader
political theory” – for example, social contract theory.[
Nonetheless,
using retribution as a sole determinant for punishment will appeal to many
people - and the high support rates for the death penalty in the United States
seems to bear this out. This is Biblical justice, ‘an eye for an eye’. [9]
Useful, but
unjust.
Arguments
can be made on utilitarian grounds to favour the use of punishment where the
outcome may not be just, but serves a useful purpose. To understand this we
need to understand how utilitarianism works – it is a system where any action
is defined as “right if it produces as much or more of an increase in happiness
of all affected by it than any alternative action, and wrong if it does not.” [10]
It is a consequentialist theory of ethics, concerned with goals.
Jeremy
Bentham (1789), a leading proponent of the theory, describes “all punishment
[as] mischief, all punishment is in itself evil.” He is discussing the evils of
restricted liberty (for those who obey the law), and the evil of fearing or
suffering punishment (by those who do not obey the law). Nonetheless, he
recognised that the law could produce an artificial harmony between the general
and individual interest – where the punishment is strong enough to outweigh the
potential benefits of a crime the balance is misery, and thus constrains a
person from offending.
The theory
has been criticised by its own logic, though. Because ‘justice’ isn’t
necessarily a relevant factor, utilitarianism might uphold severe punishments
for minor offences where the excessive sentencing would create an overall
deterrence. Nils Christie gives this example:
“[Norway has] passed a law making it
compulsory to wear seatbelts … Here are noble tasks for deterrence. Just a few
five-year sentences, and we would have done it.”
This is
plainly unjust, but potentially very useful. Some evaluations of utilitarianism
have countered this example by reference to the theory’s scale of penalties –
the need to show that some wrongs are more serious than others, otherwise there
is “a risk of either confusing common morality or flouting it and bringing the
law into contempt.” [11]
This is another part of utilitarianism’s ‘weighing’ process – if the overall
respect for law is diminished then this is large evil to be considered against
the good of ensuring compliance.
Conclusion:
a smorgasbord?
While there
is an obvious, common-sense appeal to Eckhoff’s primary assertion that
punishment should only be employed when “we find it both useful and just,” we
should recognise that his supporting arguments are based largely on moral
intuitions. Lacey complains that Eckhoff doesn’t follow his moral assertions
with “any rigorous argument either for the content of that sense of justice or
for the consequent rejection” of other theories.
When we look
at other justifications of punishment – useful/unjust, just/useless – we see
various validations that Eckhoff failed to clearly address. He concludes that
“it is thus the combined impact of utilitarian and retributivist considerations
which makes for acceptance in this and many other cases of punishment.” Yet
this seems an unusual acceptance in the wake of his attacks on both utilitarian
and retributive theories.
I agree that
there is a need to approach the problem with a “more critical opinion,” but I
think this critical opinion can be applied to Eckhoff’s own arguments. There
may in fact be scope to inflict punishments outside of Eckhoff’s area of
limitation, but there is an even more important need to question the use of
punishment at all.
[1] Duff & Simmonds Philosophy and the Criminal Law (1984).
[2] C.M.V. Clarkson Understanding Criminal Law.
[3] Taylor.
[4] Gross (1979).
[5] Profitability is less important for this discussion, but briefly is
the weighing up of gains against ‘associated losses’.
[6] From a discussion with Warren Brookbanks.
[7] Immanuel Kant The Science of Right (1790).
[8] Lacey Punishment, Justice and Consequentialism: A Reply to
Professor Eckhoff.
[9] There are even those (in the minority) who defend revenge itself as
a justification, for example: In Defense of Revenge, from Medieval
Crime and Social Control.
[10] Peter Singer, Practical Ethics.
[11] H.L.A. Hart Punishment and Responsibility (1968).
No comments:
Post a Comment